 |
SwiftVets.com Service to Country
|
View previous topic :: View next topic |
Author |
Message |
LewWaters Admin
Joined: 18 May 2004 Posts: 4042 Location: Washington State
|
Posted: Sat Apr 09, 2005 3:13 am Post subject: |
|
|
If anyone still believes a Living Will is a cure-all for this, think again. Mae Magouirk had a Living Will and it is being ignored.
Below is an excerpt from an article 10 years ago. Be careful what you wish today, it may be used against you later;
Quote: | The Will to Live
When Marjorie Nighbert entered a nursing home after having a stroke, she did not expect to be starved to death, but that is what happened when she became a victim of her own "wishes."
Like many people, she did not want her life to be prolonged when death was imminent. So Nighbert created a durable power of attorney (DPA), in which she gave her brother control over medical decisions in case she could not make them for herself. And according to the family lawyer, Nighbert said she did not want a feeding tube if she became terminally ill.
When Nighbert fell ill the nursing home followed the orders of the DPA and denied her food and water for two weeks. But then something unexpected happened: She asked to be fed. A court battle ensued, and the court ultimately upheld the nursing home's decision to deny Nighbert food and water. According to the judge, Nighbert was not competent to ask for food, and to give her food would constitute "extraordinary means."
Nighbert died on April 6, 1995. |
The Will To Live _________________ Clark County Conservative |
|
Back to top |
|
 |
Navy_Navy_Navy Admin
Joined: 07 May 2004 Posts: 5777
|
Posted: Sat Apr 09, 2005 3:28 am Post subject: |
|
|
Ohmigod, Lew!!!!
I nearly screamed out loud when I read that!
It was bad enough that Terri tried to say she wanted to live and it was ignored - but that it happened ten years ago is sickening!
I guess I've just been asleep all this time.
I can't even count how many times my heart has broken over the last few weeks. But, I can't let go of it - now that I'm awake, I know that I'm going to have to be a veritable pit-bull on this issue. _________________ ~ Echo Juliet ~
Altering course to starboard - On Fire, Keep Clear
Navy woman, Navy wife, Navy mother |
|
Back to top |
|
 |
Rdtf CNO
Joined: 13 May 2004 Posts: 2209 Location: BUSHville
|
Posted: Sat Apr 09, 2005 3:33 am Post subject: |
|
|
Hmmm ok - so how do we make it CLEAR? Maybe do the living will, cite the reasons for your decisions, and mail it to all your family and friends and yourself to show a post mark.
Who the h*** knows. |
|
Back to top |
|
 |
LewWaters Admin
Joined: 18 May 2004 Posts: 4042 Location: Washington State
|
Posted: Sat Apr 09, 2005 3:52 am Post subject: |
|
|
Doing some more digging on the Majorie Nighbert story I ran across some other mentions of it. It was reported originally by the The Washington Post National Weekly Edition, January 13, 1997, page 23. (article no longer available, that I can find) Sorry, but it just gets worse as I look.
From deep within the middle of the article, I found;
Quote: | Marjorie Nighbert signed an "advance directive" before she was hospitalized for a stroke in 1996. This document stated that she desired no "heroic measures." Based on this, her family requested that her feeding tube be removed. When Ms. Nighbert begged for food, the courts deemed her "not medically competent to ask for such a treatment," and the hospital physically restrained her in bed so that she could not pilfer food from other patients. She died ten days later. |
The Right To Die Movement Is Using Terri Schiavo Are You Next?
I have no idea what recourse we may have. I also have no idea what country I've been living in. I thought it was America where life was to be cherished, not idly thrown away. _________________ Clark County Conservative |
|
Back to top |
|
 |
SBD Admiral
Joined: 19 Aug 2004 Posts: 1022
|
Posted: Sat Apr 09, 2005 8:40 am Post subject: |
|
|
LewWaters wrote: | Doing some more digging on the Majorie Nighbert story I ran across some other mentions of it. It was reported originally by the The Washington Post National Weekly Edition, January 13, 1997, page 23. (article no longer available, that I can find) Sorry, but it just gets worse as I look.
From deep within the middle of the article, I found;
Quote: | Marjorie Nighbert signed an "advance directive" before she was hospitalized for a stroke in 1996. This document stated that she desired no "heroic measures." Based on this, her family requested that her feeding tube be removed. When Ms. Nighbert begged for food, the courts deemed her "not medically competent to ask for such a treatment," and the hospital physically restrained her in bed so that she could not pilfer food from other patients. She died ten days later. |
The Right To Die Movement Is Using Terri Schiavo Are You Next?
I have no idea what recourse we may have. I also have no idea what country I've been living in. I thought it was America where life was to be cherished, not idly thrown away. |
Here's the whole article, I will post the Supreme Court Testimony next.
The Washington Post, January 05, 1997
Could You Please Die Now? Disabled People Like Me Have Good Reason to Fear the Push for Assisted Suicide
BYLINE: Evan J. Kemp Jr.
On January 8, the Supreme Court will hear oral arguments in Glucksberg v. State of Washington v. and Vacco v. Quill. At issue is the question of whether or not "terminally ill" individuals have an inherent "right to die." And, if so, should a licensed physician be granted the legal right to assist in the "suicide" of a patient?
As the case is being argued inside the court, thousands will be keeping vigil outside the court. I will be among them.
You might ask, "Why would a conservative Republican who served as the chair of the U.S. Equal Employment Opportunity Commission in the Bush administration join Clinton Democrats, representatives of the Catholic Church, Orthodox Jews, civil rights advocates, and a large congregation of disabled and elderly people in a noisy street demonstration?"
The answer is simple: I do not believe that doctors should kill their patients.
At the outset, I must acknowledge that the right to die proponents have a certain undeniable logic to their argument. I agree with the proposition that every individual has a right to control his or her life. Unfortunately, this logic does not take into account the institutional ramifications of physician-assisted suicide and thus misses a much more basic point. In this age of soaring health care costs, I believe the right-to-die option will in evitably be transformed into a means of rationing health care.
As a matter of fact, we've already taken our first few steps down this exceedingly steep and slippery slope. At present, a patient checking into a hospital is routinely given the option of signing a "do not resuscitate" order (DNR), requesting that "heroic measures," such as cardiopulmonary resuscitation, not be taken should such measures be required to keep the person alive.
DNR consent is supposed to be voluntary. In practice, however, that has not always been the case. Some disabled people report instances in which hospitals have pressured patients -- most notably, people with disabilities, the uninsured, and the severely ill -- to sign DNR orders.
In some cases, the DNR is not explained clearly. The patient, or the patient's family or other representative, is not adequately informed of the nature of the order -- especially the fact that it is supposed to be voluntary. The DNR is often included with other routine administrative papers to be signed. This cannot be construed as "informed consent."
Joe Ehman, a news reporter in Rochester, N.Y., who uses a wheelchair, told me he was "literally hounded by social workers" to sign a DNR when he was hospitalized in 1995 for back surgery. "A few hours after surgery, still delirious from the anesthesia and from postsurgical morphine and demerol, I had to hear from yet another social worker who wanted to force-feed me a DNR. I mustered my strength and screamed, 'I'm 30 years old. I don't want to die!' "
Maria Matzik, a woman in her thirties who lives and works in Dayton, Ohio, says she had a frightening battle with nurses during a 1993 hospital stay. "They kept asking me to sign a DNR order," she told me. "When I wouldn't sign it, they said it didn't matter anyway. Because I use a ventilator, they told me nothing would be done if I had a cardiac arrest." Matzik escaped that fate, but others have not.
Marjorie Nighbert, a 76-year-old Florida woman, was hospitalized in 1996 after a stroke. Before her hospital admission, she signed an advance directive that no "heroic measures" should be employed to save her life. On the basis of that directive and at the request of her family, the hospital denied Nighbert's requests for food and water, according to reports in the Northwest Florida Daily News. A hurriedly convened hospital ethics committee ruled that she was "not medically competent to ask for such a treatment." Until her death more than 10 days later, Nighbert was restrained in her bed to prevent her from raiding other patients' food trays.
The larger point is that, in evaluating the right-to-die movement, one should not overlook the fundamental importance of money. In the Glucksberg v. State of Washington decision, federal judge Stephen Reinhardt tried to put the best possible face on the economic pressures involved in life and death decisions: " . . . in a society in which the costs of protracted health care can be so exorbitant, we are reluctant to say that it is improper for competent, terminally ill adults to take the economic welfare of their families and loved ones into consideration."
When it comes to spending money on health care, however, "families and loved ones" are often not in a position to call the shots. Insurance companies, hospitals, nursing homes and HMOs are -- and they would prefer that the dirty little secret of money be kept out of the public debate about assisted suicide. After all, it's much easier for them to justify their actions on the basis of humanitarian principle than financial self-interest. Once physician-assisted suicide is given the sanction of law, our health care institutions are likely to devise contractual mechanisms that make sure members of targeted groups die as efficiently as possible.
All of this will be justified by the holy grail of the right-to-die movement: "choice." But the laws of economics virtually guarantee that, in practice, those who "choose" assisted suicide will disproportionately come from the lower end of the socioeconomic ladder: people without health insurance, as well as from people who are said to possess a low "quality of life" -- i.e., people with disabilities.
As former Surgeon General C. Everett Koop declared at a Washington press conference in November, "Toleration of doctor-assisted suicide can lead to acceptance of involuntary euthanasia."
Koop recently agreed to speak at Wednesday's protest on the Supreme Court steps, saying that he was "very pleased to have this opportunity to address the disability community which is so threatened by physician-assisted suicide."
As a disabled person, I am especially sensitive to the "quality of life" rationale that is frequently introduced in the debate. For the past 47 years I have lived with a progressive neuromuscular disease that first began to manifest itself when I was 12. My disease, Kugelburg Weylander Syndrome, has no known cure, and I have no hope for "recovery."
Upon diagnosis, my parents were informed by the physicians treating me that I would die within two years. Later, another group of physicians was certain that I would live only to the age of 18. Yet here I am at age 59, continuing to have an extraordinarily high quality of life.
And my case is by no means unique. The majority of families I have encountered in my lifetime, and who have been close enough to share details of their extended family life, have had at least one member who defied the medical establishment by living a far longer and more productive life than expected. Should we permit the medical establishment to assist these individuals with disabilities to die before their time at the hands of their physicians? I don't think so.
If the Supreme Court decides to decriminalize physician-assisted suicide, the next question to arise will be how to pay for the service. If the suicide services, dubbed "obitiatry" by Dr. Jack Kevorkian, become billable, those services could dovetail all too well with our nation's current drive to cut health care costs. Health maintenance organizations may view the cost of obitiatry as especially cost-effective in that the practice will require neither referrals to specialists nor repeat visits to physicians' offices.
In managed-care parlance, the portion of the premium dollar spent on medical care is called the "medical-loss ratio." Insurance companies and health maintenance organizations could cut that ratio by providing assisted suicide rather than bypass surgeries and the like. Afterall, many people are cheaper dead than alive.
The American Medical Association has twice affirmed its opposition to physician-assisted suicide and recently filed an amicus brief with the Supreme Court. The AMA wishes for physicians to maintain their role as healers, and not to become potential killers, even for reasons of mercy.
The experience of Nazi Germany is relevant here, not because the advocates of assisted suicide are incipient fascists (they're not) but because of the historical fact that the Holocaust had its beginnings in the systematic elimination of Germans with disabilities. As Hugh Gregory Gallagher noted in his 1990 book, "By Trust Betrayed: Physicians, Patients and the License to Kill in the Third Reich," Adolf Hitler's order of September 1939 called for physicians to assist in the killings of citizens with illnesses and disabilities. Nazi propagandists, led by a small number of physicians, said that such citizens were "useless eaters" and "life unworthy of life." Today American health planners, while driven by a very different ideology, also speak a dehumanizing language about "health care consumers" and the dubious "quality of life" of our citizens with illnesses and disabilities.
From where I sit, it is undeniably clear that giving physician-assisted suicide the sanction of law will have unintended consequences which vastly outweigh any benefits that might accrue. As Koop puts it, "Society must not allow doctors to be killers as well as healers."
Evan Kemp, former chairman of the Equal Employment Opportunity Commission, is senior partner of Evan Kemp Associates, Inc., a health and mobility company owned and operated by disabled people.
What One Appeals Court Said
The right-to-die case that the Supreme Court will hear this week originated in 1994 when Harold Glucksberg and three other Seattle doctors specializing in care for terminally ill patients challenged a Washington state law forbidding assisted suicide. Last March the 12-judge panel of the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals upheld the doctors in a decision now known as Glucksberg v. State of Washington.
The majority opinion, written by Judge Stephen Reinhardt and signed by eight other judges, relied heavily on the Supreme Court's previous rulings in two cases upholding a woman's right to abortion, Planned Parenthood v. Casey and Cruzan v. State of Missouri. A dissenting opinion, written by Judge Robert Beezer and supported by two of his colleagues, argued that the issue should be decided by legislatures and people, not judges.
Reinhardt's Ruling: Casey and Cruzan provide persuasive evidence that the Constitution encompasses a due process liberty interest in controlling the time and manner of one's death -- that there is, in short, a constitutionally recognized "right to die." Our conclusion is strongly influenced by, but not limited to, the plight of mentally competent, terminally ill adults. We are influenced as well by the plight of others, such as those whose existence is reduced to a vegetative state or a permanent and irreversible state of unconsciousness.
Our conclusion that there is a liberty interest in determining the time and manner of one's death does not mean that there is a concomitant right to exercise that interest in all circumstances or to do so free from state regulation. To the contrary, we explicitly recognize that some prohibitory and regulatory state action is fully consistent with constitutional principles.
In short, finding a liberty interest constitutes a critical first step toward answering the question before us. The determination that must now be made is whether the state's attempt to curtail the exercise of that interest is constitutionally justified.
Beezer's Dissent: To declare a constitutional right to physician-assisted suicide would be to impose upon the nation a repeal of local laws. Such a declaration would also usurp states' rights to regulate and further the practice of medicine, insofar as a right to physician-assisted suicide flies in the face of well-established state laws governing the medical profession. Finally, the rationales under which we are asked to create this right fail adequately to distinguish physician-assisted suicide as a unique category. If physician-assisted suicide for mentally competent, terminally ill adults is made a constitutional right, voluntary euthanasia for weaker patients, unable to self-terminate, will soon follow. After voluntary euthanasia, it is but a short step to a "substituted judgment" or "best interests" analysis for terminally ill patients who have not yet expressed their constitutionally sanctioned desire to be dispatched from this world. This is the sure and inevitable path, as the Dutch experience has amply demonstrated. It is not a path I would start down.
SBD |
|
Back to top |
|
 |
SBD Admiral
Joined: 19 Aug 2004 Posts: 1022
|
Posted: Sat Apr 09, 2005 8:47 am Post subject: |
|
|
The Washington Post, January 09, 1997
EXCERPTS FROM THE SUPREME COURT DECISION ON PHYSICIAN-ASSISTED SUICIDE
Following are excerpts from the oral arguments before the Supreme Court yesterday on doctor-assisted suicide in the twin cases of Washington v. Glucksberg and Vacco v. Quill.
William L. Williams, senior assistant attorney general of the state of Washington: We are here today representing the people of the state of Washington to defend their legislative policy judgment to prohibit assisted suicide. . . . The issue here today is whether the Constitution requires that the social policy developed by Washington voters must be supplanted by a far different social policy, a constitutionally recognized right to physician-assisted suicide that is contrary to our traditions and overrides the important state interests that are served by the Washington statute. . . .
Respondents offer a line that is unstable and inconsistent with the concept of ordered liberty. It is inconsistent with liberty in three respects. First, it is limited to a very few of our citizens. Secondly, those few must justify their exercise of this so-called constitutional right. Thirdly . . . this right, if it is to be exercised at all, if it is to be recognized at all, must be closely regulated. And their equal protection argument demonstrates just how unstable the line is, because they suggest that flowing from this court's assumed recognition of a right to refuse treatment in the Cruzan case, there is a seamless stream of constitutional rights that flows from that decision.
Justice Ruth Bader Ginsburg: In the Cruzan case, the court recognized a liberty interest and yet it upheld restrictive legislation. . . . So couldn't one take the same approach here, there is a liberty interest, but because of the risks and dangers involved, considerable state regulation is permissible?
Williams: . . . The problem that that would create by recognizing a liberty interest is that many states are considering whether to move the line by legislation -- in fact, our sister state of Oregon has done just that. . . . A recognition of a liberty interest may limit their flexibility to deal with this complicated area. We agree that, even if you find the existence of a liberty interest, that the same important state interests that were present in Cruzan are present in this case and would justify the statute nonetheless. . . .
Justice Sandra Day O'Connor: What are the state interests you would argue support the law here in the event that a liberty interest is recognized?
Williams: There are three important state interests that are involved. The first one is life, which includes the state's interest in . . . preventing suicide. And, in the hierarchy of constitutional value, certainly the protection of life is the highest. . . . The second one is to prevent abuse and undue influence, and certainly the risk is higher in the physician-assisted suicide context than it is in the refusal of treatment context. And thirdly, there is a strong interest in regulating the medical profession. Precisely because physicians have the capacity to injure or perhaps cause the death of their patients, the state has an important interest in maintaining a clear line between physicians as healers and curers and physicians as instruments of death of their patients. . . .
Chief Justice William H. Rehnquist: It would be very difficult to assume a liberty interest and rule in your favor in this case, would it not? Because if we assume a liberty interest but nonetheless say that, even assuming a liberty interest, a state can prohibit it entirely, that would be rather a conundrum.
Williams: . . . I disagree to this extent: I believe the state, the same important state interests that were implicated in the Cruzan case are implicated here but more strongly. . . .
Rehnquist: But in Cruzan what we were dealing with was a state rule that said you had to prove a certain thing by clear and convincing evidence. Here we're not dealing with any sort of an evidentiary rule, we're dealing with an outright prohibition.
Williams: That's correct. . . .
Justice Antonin Scalia: I suppose that proclaiming a liberty interest is cost-free so long as you can proclaim them and then say, however they can be outweighed by various social policies adopted by the states. We can say there's a liberty interest in murdering people, however it's outweighed by the state's interest in preserving the lives of its citizens. I guess we could do that, couldn't we?
Williams: That's true. . . . The other point I was going to make . . . there is the Oregon Employment Security Division versus Smith case, the peyote case, where the court there, involving a much stronger interest, the First Amendment free exercise of religion, nonetheless upheld an absolute ban on the use of drugs because of the state's important interest in its drug enforcement policies. . . .
Walter E. Dellinger, acting solicitor general of the United States:
Justice Sandra O'Connor: . . . It's your brief that takes the position that there is a liberty interest, but nonetheless, the law should be upheld.
Dellinger: That is correct. . . . We think it's not critical to the case, but we urge you to acknowledge that a person states a cognizable liberty interest when he or she alleges that the state is imposing severe pain and suffering or has adopted a rule which prevents someone from the only means of relieving that pain and suffering. This is a narrow liberty interest. . . . [W]e do not agree with the 9th Circuit's conclusion that there is a general liberty interest in dying. . . . States have long had laws that affirm the value of life by prohibiting anyone from promoting or assisting a suicide and I believe that no one disputes the constitutionality of those laws as a general matter. The actual question before the court is whether the Constitution compels an exception to those laws here. In our view it does not. . . . While the individual stories are heartrending . . . it's important for this court to recognize that, if you were to affirm the judgments below, lethal medication could be proposed as a treatment, not just to those in severe pain, but to every competent terminally ill personal in the country.
Justice David H. Souter: . . . I don't know how to weight this probability and this risk. Help me out on that.
Dellinger: . . . No American jurisdiction has ever recognized physician-assisted suicide as a lawful practice. So that there's no experiential basis for the conclusion that there could be adequate safeguards to protect those who are suffering from depression and who may request lethal medication because of untreated depression. . . .
Souter: . . . [T]hat might be a . . . perfectly legitimate argument for saying that . . . the court should wait until it can know more. . . . before it passes ultimate judgment.
Dellinger: In light of the multiple uncertainties we refer to in our brief, it would be I think a grave mistake for the court to impose on 50 states such a marked transformation that had never been tried by even a single state.
Scalia: But you say . . . there is a liberty interest which . . . tosses the whole matter into this court so that it's up to us to decide whether indeed the states are right or wrong that this is a dangerous practice. And, if we think they're wrong, then . . . the liberty interest must prevail. . . .
Dellinger: Yes. . . . I would refer you [to] the New York state task force address. . . . [T]hey note that one can deposit ideal cases in which all recommended safeguards would be satisfied: Patients would be screened for depression and offered treatment, effective pain medication would be available, and all patients would have a supportive, committed family and doctor. Yet the reality of existing medical practice in doctors' offices and hospitals cannot generally meet these expectations. . . . The systemic dangers are dramatic. The least costly treatment for any illness is lethal medication. And the medical profession tells you in briefs. . . . that we have a system in which we are struggling to try to provide proper treatment for pain and for depression. Someone who is not treated for pain is not in a position to make the kind of decisions they need to be forced to make here.
Kathryn L. Tucker on behalf of those seeking to allow physician-assisted suicide in Washington: . . . This case presents the question whether dying citizens in full possession of their mental faculties at the threshold of death due to terminal illness have the liberty to choose to cross that threshold in a humane and dignified manner. . . .
Rehnquist: . . . [T]here is not an issue here. . . . [I]t's that they want assistance from a physician to do it, that's what we're arguing about.
Tucker: That's correct. . . . And the reason why we are focused on that is because these dying patients want a peaceful death, they want a humane death and they want a dignified death. And, in order to access that kind of death they need the assistance of their physician. . . .
Scalia: . . . [W]hy is it limited to those on the threshold of death? I mean suppose . . . the doctor says you're going to be in terrible pain for 10 years. . . . Why shouldn't I have the right to suicide.
Tucker: . . . [A] patient who is confronting death . . . has a very different choice than the one you posit. This individual does not have a choice between living and dying. This dying patient whose dying process has begun and is underway, this individual has only the choice of how to die. Will that death be brutal, will that death be peaceful.
Ginsburg: . . . [W]hat about the person who is in such agony that that person is not able to assist in her own suicide so she needs the doctor or the nurse to administer the lethal dose. Isn't that person in a more sympathetic situation than the one you're describing?
Tucker: . . . [Y]ou are describing someone who just can't bring themself to do it. . . . Self-administration does address an important state concern here, and that's the concern of voluntariness. We agree that this decision should always rest with the individual and that it should be authentic and voluntary. And to require the individual to not only make this choice but then to take the final act, we believe assures voluntariness in an important way.
Scalia: And you are saying that the state can tell individuals that they may not take their own life.
Tucker: Yes . . . absolutely.
Scalia: . . . I don't understand what the limit is. . . .
Tucker: The terminally ill patient does not have the expectation of a continued life beyond this very short interim before death. Certainly the patient . . . that would choose to endure that period of suffering before death and find it enjoyable and find it fulfilling should be permitted to make that choice, and many will make that choice. . . . But for some patients, based on their values and beliefs formed over a lifetime, that additional quantum of suffering is intolerable to their personhood. . . . This I think will enable me to respond to the solicitor general's comment that what we're dealing with here is simply a liberty interest in avoiding pain and suffering. That absolutely trivializes the claim. We have a constellation of interest, each of great constitutional dimension. Yes, there is the interest in avoiding pain and suffering. . . . The second in the constellation of interest is decisional autonomy, and the third in the constellation that has bearing here is the interest in bodily integrity. Each of those separate interests is of constitutional dimension and each has bearing here. . . .
Ginsburg: . . . You said formed over a lifetime. That's surely not part of your calculus, it could be someone who never thought a moment about this but is in terrible agony and would fit your terminal in your terminal illness category. . . . Isn't it possible that such a person could at one time, even for a period of days, say I want to die, I want to die, and didn't get the assistance, lives on, and says I'm glad that I didn't do that. . . .
Tucker: That's possible. . . . I do think that it would be permissible for the state . . . to impose a waiting period. . . . We are asking simply that this court recognize the vital liberty interest at stake and that it is a protected choice but not asking this court to engage in legislation, we are not asking this court to promulgate a code for regulation of the practice. We do think it should be left to the states.
Rehnquist: You're not asking that now. But surely that's what the next couple of generations are going to have to deal with, what regulations are permissible and whatnot if we uphold your position here.
Tucker: I think not. . . . We think it's appropriate for that experimentation to occur in the states. There is substantial consensus as to what form of regulation would be appropriate.
O'Connor: . . . There is no doubt that . . . if we upheld your position, it would result in a flow of cases through the court system for heaven knows how long. I wanted to ask you whether it should enter the balance of state interests versus the interests of the patient here, that this is an issue that every one of us faces, young or old, male or female, whatever it might be. And all of us who are citizens and authorized to vote can certainly participate through that process in the development of state laws in this area. . . .
Tucker: I take your point . . . but I do think that we are dealing with an issue, the literature is extensive on this, that ours is a culture of denial of death. And that people in our society do not deal with their own mortality until confronted with their death and because of that I do think we have some concerns that the political process would not be expected to work in a usual fashion. . . .
Souter: . . . If, in fact, you are right about the pervasiveness of the denial of death, that denial simply reflects the way we are. And it seems to me that it's a perfectly legitimate reflection when it finds its way into the legislative process. Is there a flaw in that reasoning?
Tucker: Well, I think what I was getting at . . . is that because there's the denial and people do not confront mortality until faced up against it, you do not have an activist component that is able to address that in the legislative process. When a patient is on their death bed, they don't have the ability to become politically active. . . .
Justice Anthony M. Kennedy: . . . [I]t's a matter of defining the liberty. And this is a question of ethics and of morals and of allocation of resources and of our commitment to treat the elderly and infirm. And surely legislators have much more flexibility and a much greater capacity to absorb those kind of arguments and make those decisions than we do. You're asking us in effect to declare unconstitutional the law of 50 states.
Tucker: We're asking this court to simply recognize the vital nature of this liberty and to leave to state experimentation the regulatory process and the state --
Dennis Vacco, attorney general of New York state: The question in this case is whether the state must remain neutral in the face of a decision of one of its citizens to help another kill herself. The 2nd Circuit below said yes, as a matter of equal protection. It is New York's view, however, that the Constitution does not require this to be the case.
Indeed, equal protection is not implicated at all in this case. Patients who withdraw from life support are not similarly situated to terminally ill people who are seeking physician-assisted suicide.
Ginsburg: . . . The distinction that the 2nd Circuit fastened on was the terminally ill person who says no more life supports, I want to die, and the person who wants a pill that will achieve the same end. So let's narrow it to what that court was dealing with and tell us why that court was wrong.
Vacco: . . . The people . . . are not similarly situated. In the first context the individual who is at the . . . end stages of their life as the 2nd Circuit defined it, are exercising their right . . . to refuse treatment. That right which has been recognized for centuries as springing from the common law, the right of being free from bodily interference, the right to be free from battery, [the] right to be let alone.
On the contrary, and in contrast, are those individuals who are not asserting a right, that is . . . their rights to bodily integrity, but instead attempting to assert, as the plaintiff respondents in this case are claiming, that there is some right to have a third party, in this instance physicians, help kill themselves. And we believe that these two acts are clearly distinguishable. . . .
Ginsburg: You say you've distinguished the drugs at the last hour or hours of life. But we're told that this treatment, whatever you want to call it, that inevitably will lead to death, will do so in a matter of days, not hours. And that that goes on. And how is that rationally distinguishable from a pill that will work --
Vacco: . . . It's rationally distinguishable because it is consistent medical practice. . . . Providing drugs specifically and solely for the purpose of killing someone has never been embraced by the medical profession.
Souter: . . . I take it you mean that, once you accept the right of a patient to withdraw all life support including hydration and feeding, then the only way to prevent excruciating pain as the person nears death is with these extraordinarily high dosages of painkiller that induce coma. . . .
Vacco: Yes. And indeed the subsequent administration of the palliative care drugs is consistent with the long-standing notion of the double effect, that the drugs in that instance are not being administered for the purpose of causing the death, they are administered in the context of the post refusal or post withdrawal of treatment palliative care of the patient. . . .
Souter: Is . . . the reason you draw the line ultimately between ending the life support and the affirmative act of giving the pill, is it essentially a line that depends on the argument for risk of abuse?
Vacco: The principal . . . justification indeed, one of the most compelling reasons, state interest, is the risk of abuse. And that abuse is going to manifest itself in a variety --
Souter: Well, why isn't there a risk of abuse that those who might stand to profit or at least themselves risk further discomfort by an early death for a person on life support will try to coerce or persuade that person to end life support when it really isn't a voluntary decision, why isn't that a risk?
Vacco: . . . There is no question that in certain instances there is an overlapping of the risk of abuse. But we believe in the context of physician-assisted suicide. The risk of abuse is far greater. . . .
Souter: Is it far greater with respect to those who, in fact, are truly terminally ill? Or is it far greater because it affects a broader class than the terminally ill?
Vacco: It's for both reasons. . . . Who is to define terminally ill, how do we define it with such certainty? . . .
Acting Solicitor General Dellinger: The issue that is raised with more saliency in New York is that even if the state may, as a general matter, legitimately prohibit the granting of lethal medication, the fact that these state permit practices that are in the respondents' view medically, ethically, and morally indistinguishable from lethal medication requires that these states also do that.
We do not agree that the states' interest in prohibiting lethal medication is lessened by the fact that the state permits competent terminally ill adults to refuse unwanted medical treatment. There is an important common sense distinction between withdrawing artificial support so that a disease will progress to its inevitable end and providing chemicals to be used to kill someone. . . . The historic distinction between killing someone and letting them die is so powerful that we believe that it fully suffices here. . . .
Ginsburg: . . . If you could, deal with the argument that's been made about winks and nods, that all of this is really a great sham because physician-assisted suicide goes on for anybody who is sophisticated enough to want it.
Dellinger: . . . We looked and we don't know what the evidentiary basis is for that.
We do not know any basis for the conclusion that pain medication's being deliberately offered in excess of what is necessary to relieve pain in order to cause death.
Oral argument of Laurence H. Tribe on behalf of those seeking to allow physician-assisted suicide in New York: . . . What happens to people as they degenerate is that they are given all kinds of treatments and they accept them, and this idea that at the end you're either in this closed class of people who luckily have a plug that can be pulled, or you're in some other group, is a fantasy. Every case, or virtually every case --
Kennedy: Well, I suppose it's based on the distinction between allowing events to take their own course and third-person intervention, which the law has recognized in the law of torts and in most of its other substantive areas for centuries.
Tribe: None of these patients is in a state of nature. They're in a hospital or a hospice. And they're receiving chemotherapy, radiation, bone marrow transplants.
Kennedy: Yes. But when a person on a life support system wants the systems discontinued, she is not committing suicide, which is what you said earlier. She is not doing that, she's allowing nature to take its course.
Tribe: If I could explore nature just for a moment. Of course, it's up to the state of New York how to characterize whether she's committing suicide. But . . . the government's characterization can't control the constitutional analysis. . . .
Justice Stephen G. Breyer: . . . However you define the liberty interest, there are tremendously difficult procedural questions of what would be the safeguards of voluntariness, a much more difficult question . . . than what you might think. And how do you decide terminal condition. And what about the relationship of laws like double effect and all of that area. . . . What's your response to the proposition that these different groups, interacting with the legislature, are far more suited . . . to come up with an answer than a court writing a constitutional provision.
Tribe: . . . It seems to me that what we have here, setting aside the issue of liberty for the moment, and I don't understand frankly the solicitor general's position it can be a "now you see it, now you don't" liberty. . . . In a sense there are 50 laboratories out there. The famous state laboratories of Justice Brandeis. . . . These laboratories, however, are now operating largely with the lights out. They're operating with the lights out because it's not just New York. What I've described is as far as I've been able to determine through research of the law of at least 35 or maybe 40 states. . . . In all of these states what they do, and it's a logic that collapses on itself, is they combine two understandable principles.
One principle is you can medicate someone to make them comfortable, to reduce their pain even when you are pretty sure -- or even when you know, as long as that's not your real intent -- that it will hasten their death.
The other principle is that a person has the right to say, no, don't give me that feeding tube. Once I've got it, it may be hard to take it out, and anyway, leave me alone. You combine these two and the logic so remarkably collapses in the case of terminal sedation, which is overwhelmingly documented everywhere in the country, it's not some sneaky practice. . . .
Justice John Paul Stevens: Tell us what you think the liberty interest is.
Tribe: The liberty interest in this case is the liberty, when facing imminent and inevitable death, not to be forced by the government to endure a degree of pain and suffering that one can relieve only by being completely unconscious. Not to be forced into that choice, that the liberty is the freedom, at this threshold at the end of life, not to be a creature of the state but to have some voice in the question of how much pain one is really going through.
Souter: Why does the voice just arrive when death is imminent?
Tribe: The court's jurisprudence has identified, I think for good reason, that life, though it feels continuous to many of us, has certain critical thresholds: Birth, marriage, child-bearing. I think death is one of those thresholds. That is, it is the last chapter of one's life after all. . . .
GRAPHIC: Photo, larry morris , Supporters of the Hemlock Society share the Supreme Court plaza with John Tassone, who is opposed to euthanasia.
SBD |
|
Back to top |
|
 |
LewWaters Admin
Joined: 18 May 2004 Posts: 4042 Location: Washington State
|
Posted: Sat Apr 09, 2005 2:53 pm Post subject: |
|
|
Thanks, SBD. I've saved those along with others I've been finding. It's hard to believe this has been going on so long and relatively quietly.
Sadly, many who think it's humane to authorize a "right to die," don't realize what a short step it is to "obligation to die."
Much like those encouraging suicide bombers, we never see the main advocates for this practice utilizing it either. _________________ Clark County Conservative |
|
Back to top |
|
 |
|
|
You cannot post new topics in this forum You cannot reply to topics in this forum You cannot edit your posts in this forum You cannot delete your posts in this forum You cannot vote in polls in this forum
|
Powered by phpBB © 2001, 2005 phpBB Group
|